{"id":3169,"date":"2019-06-04T03:04:39","date_gmt":"2019-06-04T03:04:39","guid":{"rendered":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/?p=3169"},"modified":"2019-06-07T15:34:31","modified_gmt":"2019-06-07T15:34:31","slug":"physicians-conscience-case-calls-for-rethink-of-reasonable-limits","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/physicians-conscience-case-calls-for-rethink-of-reasonable-limits\/","title":{"rendered":"Losing Rights in the Balance"},"content":{"rendered":"\n

Back in 2008, the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario (CPSO) issued a new policy entitled \u201cPhysicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code<\/em>.\u201d That policy informed physicians that they should be prepared to \u201cset aside their personal beliefs\u201d in providing healthcare. It warned that the Human Rights Code <\/em>has no defence for discriminatory refusals of medical services, \u201ceven if the refusal is based on the physician\u2019s moral or religious belief.\u201d The policy did not explain how to determine whether a refusal to provide a service involved unlawful discrimination. Refusing to provide a medical service because of the nature of the service, not the identity of the patient, is usually not unlawful discrimination.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

The policy became a lightning rod for controversy and attracted forceful criticism from the Ontario Medical Association (OMA) \u2013 the provincial advocacy body for physicians. The OMA objected to the Policy\u2019s failure to even mention the Charter<\/em>freedoms of conscience and religion, and expressed its confidence that physicians will provide their patients with appropriate care and comply with the Human Rights Code <\/em>without a CPSO policy on the matter. The OMA cautioned against publishing any such policy, in fact, as a CPSO policy had the \u201cpotential to misstate the law in this area.\u201d If only our courts shared such rule-of-law concerns.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

A few weeks ago, the Ontario Court of Appeal upheld<\/a> a modified version of the \u201cHuman Rights Policy,\u201d along with the CPSO\u2019s newer \u201cMedical Aid in Dying Policy,\u201d both of which require objecting physicians to either provide an effective referral<\/em>\u2013 referrals to a willing, available provider \u2013 or to provide the service themselves if there is insufficient time for a referral. These policies were challenged for violating freedom of conscience and religion. The Court of Appeal, like the Divisional Court, found that the CPSO policies infringed on freedom of religion, but that these infringements were justified, pursuant to the objective of promoting \u201cequitable access to health care\u201d. Both courts concluded that it was unnecessary to consider freedom of conscience. <\/p>\n\n\n\n

These policies are not directly binding. Rather, these policies are meant to be used as evidence of what is expected of physicians in professional discipline hearings. So, the policies are not formal rules of professional conduct. Nor are they authoritative explanations of what the Human Rights Code<\/em>actually requires of physicians. Rather, they are the CPSO\u2019s take on what human rights values imply for professional practice. Never mind that the CPSO could not find a single person who had been unable to obtain a desired service or was subjected to undue delay because of a conscientious objection. Never mind that in a genuine case of unlawful discrimination (based on things like sex, race, age, etc), a patient could bring a human rights complaint to a Human Rights Tribunal. The CPSO argued successfully that without these policies, or even with policies that were more accommodating of conscience, it \u201creasonably apprehended\u201d that patients could<\/em>face delays in accessing legally available services.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

Before I get to more rule-of-law-related problems with this decision, let me just say that I think the Court of Appeal reached the wrong substantive outcome. I don\u2019t think it should be unlawful (or cause for professional discipline) for a physician to conscientiously refuse to provide a requested service. Nor do I think a physician should be personally obligated to connect a patient with a willing, available provider. There are other ways to promote access to legally available services that are less infringing of freedom of conscience and religion, even if they are less convenient for the government. The objective of \u201censuring access\u201d must yield to freedom of conscience, within a certain scope. This is, after all, a fundamental freedom<\/em>.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

Our courts would do well to apply the approach proposed by ONCA Justices Miller and Lauwers (neither of whom presided in this case) and interpret \u201creasonable limits\u201d in section 1 of the Charter<\/em>differently: rather than reading Charter <\/em>rights very broadly and then saying (as a matter of course) that violations <\/em>of these rights may be justified <\/em>by weighing or balancing various policy objectives proportionally, judges should instead decide whether a Charter<\/em>claim falls within or outside the scope of that right \u2013 that is, within its reasonable and demonstrably justified limits.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

So, for example, actively misleading a patient or withholding information about the availability of a service \u2013 may be determined to fall outside the reasonable limits (i.e. \u201cboundaries\u201d or \u201cscope\u201d) of the Charter <\/em>freedom of conscience. But if, for example, it falls within the scope of a the freedom of conscience to refuse, for example, to euthanize a patient or to provide an effective referral for the same (which was, until recently, a crime), then requiring a physician to do so cannot be justified by some ill-defined, contextually variant, unpredictable, and inevitably subjective \u201cweighing\u201d of various competing factors selected by the CPSO and its lawyers for litigation purposes or determined ex post facto<\/em>by the courts.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

So, hypothetically, if all <\/em>physicians in Ontario were conscientiously opposed to euthanizing a patient (in reality, many are), the government would not be justified in coercing them to do so. If ensuring access to \u201cassisted dying\u201d were so important to the government of the day, it would have to pursue other non-Charter<\/em>-infringing means of achieving this, such as permitting nurses to provide assisted dying, or even recruiting and training people specifically for this task. If nobody <\/em>were willing to do it, however, the person wanting to be euthanized would have no recourse, and rightly so. The Carter <\/em>decision striking down the criminal prohibition did not create a positive Charter <\/em>right vis-\u00e0-vis the state to be provided \u201caid in dying,\u201d let alone a positive right vis-\u00e0-vis an individual physician, a right that would override the latter\u2019s freedom of conscience or religion. You don\u2019t have a right to what others have no duty to give you.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

The Court of Appeal\u2019s approach to the fundamental Charter<\/em>freedoms in this case seems flippant. Freedom of religion is talked about like it is merely one factor among many others to be considered, weighed, and balanced, with no special weight or priority. In fact, in the Court\u2019s view it effectively carries less weight than the vague policy objective of \u201cequitable access to legally available services.\u201d This is despite the court finding \u201cno direct evidence that access to health care is a problem caused by physicians\u2019 religious objections\u201d (ONCA decision, para 42). <\/p>\n\n\n\n

Moreover, in contrast to the point I made above about Carter <\/em>not creating a positive right to assisted dying or other objectionable procedures, the Court of Appeal in its CPSO <\/em>decision says that access to medical aid in dying, abortion, and other services \u201cengages\u201d Charter <\/em>section 7 rights (para 166) \u2013 apparently, positive rights \u2013 without explaining or defending this momentous claim, which pits the Charter <\/em>against itself. <\/p>\n\n\n\n

Tellingly, the Court also decides that it is unnecessary to even consider the freedom of conscience claim, since the same section 1 \u201cbalancing\u201d exercise that it applied to freedom of religion would apply to conscience anyway. The Court seems to assign little importance to freedom of conscience in general, noting that conscientious objections \u201cand any resulting psychological concern<\/em>\u201d result from physicians\u2019 own choices. Meanwhile, the court found that patients who encounter a doctor who conscientiously opposes the service they seek (like abortion or euthanasia) may experience real \u201cpsychological stress<\/em>\u201d and injury to dignity. <\/p>\n\n\n\n

Turning Charter <\/em>fundamental freedom cases into contests of comparative subjective stress and insult would, in my view, utterly undo the Charter<\/em>. The reason that conscience, belief, religion, and expression are Charter<\/em>freedoms is not because restricting them can cause stress. We cannot censor someone based on the \u201ccalculation\u201d that his personal stress would be less than the collective stress he might cause by speaking his mind. Similarly, we cannot discipline physicians for not participating in euthanasia or abortion because some people might feel judged or upset by the fact that a physician morally disapproves of their preferred choice of \u201ctreatment.\u201d These are fundamental freedoms, the building blocks of a free society, which permit individuals to live with integrity and societies to seek after truth and justice.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

The Court did yet more damage to fundamental freedoms jurisprudence in this case. While effectively inventing a positive right to be provided with legally available medical services \u2013 including those that used to be criminal and contrary to the Hippocratic Oath \u2013 the Court states flatly that physicians have \u201cno right, let alone a constitutional right, to practice medicine.\u201d <\/p>\n\n\n\n

Consider, in contrast, the Supreme Court of Canada\u2019s statement in Roncarelli v Duplessis <\/em>(1959):<\/p>\n\n\n\n

It is a matter of vital importance that a public administration that can refuse to allow a person to enter or continue a calling which, in the absence of regulation, would be free and legitimate, should be conducted with complete impartiality and integrity; and that the grounds for refusing or cancelling a permit should unquestionably be such, and such only, as are incompatible with the purposes envisaged by the statute [\u2026].<\/em><\/p><\/blockquote>\n\n\n\n

In the CPSO <\/em>case, it is not clear what statutory provision the CPSO is relying on as the basis for its Charter<\/em>-infringing policies. Its objective of \u201cequitable access to health care\u201d seems to be an amalgam of human rights \u201cvalues\u201d as it sees them and the general goal of access to health care. The Regulated Health Professions Act <\/em>says that the CPSO and Minister of Health must work to ensure that Ontarians have access to adequate numbers of competent physicians, but these policies were not adopted in response to evidence of a lack of access to care. The CPSO cited a \u201creasonable apprehension\u201d of delay in access to defend the Human Rights Policy after the fact, but that policy was about the CPSO\u2019s take on discrimination, not timely access.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

The Court also states that \u201cthe potential for conflict between a physician\u2019s religious beliefs and the Policies, and any resulting psychological concern,\u00a0results from<\/em> a conscious choice to practice in circumstances in which such a conflict could arise.\u201d (Emphasis added; para 50. The ONCA generally relies on the reasons of the court below: see paras. 8, 48-50, 169 of the ONCA ruling.)<\/p>\n\n\n\n

This puts the blame on physicians for having conscientious objections to these recently adopted policies. Imagine a court saying, in response to a section 2(b) claim, \u201cThe conflict with your freedom of expression results from a conscious choice by you to express your beliefs.\u201d<\/p>\n\n\n\n

The fact that this is a freedom of conscience and religion claim, not a freedom of expression claim, should make no difference. The fact that the context is that of a regulated profession matters, but not in the way these ONCA judges seem to think. A person does not have a positive right to practice medicine or any other profession, but a person does (or ought to) enjoy the freedom to pursue a profession, and to practice a profession for which he is duly licensed and qualified, without being required to violate his conscience or religion as a prerequisite for becoming or remaining licensed to practice that profession. As I said before, there are limits. A freedom of religion claim to perform female genital mutilation for example, should fall outside of the reasonable limits on that freedom. (Notably, this is a negative restriction and not a compulsion to take positive action.) But such a limit is discrete, intelligible, and serves a clearly defined purpose: to prevent an action the legislature has judged to be unethical, harmful, and in violation of another\u2019s rights. The individual who does not<\/em>provide euthanasia or effective referrals, conversely, can be accommodated. He poses no threat.<\/p>\n\n\n\n

The Charter <\/em>preamble says that Canada is built on principles recognizing the \u201csupremacy of God and the rule of law\u201d. This case illustrates how, as we disregard the rule of law, fundamental freedoms diminish. Our courts have been section 1 into a highly subjective and indeterminate \u201cbalancing\u201d exercise. We need to do better.<\/p>\n","protected":false},"excerpt":{"rendered":"

Back in 2008, the College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario (CPSO) issued a new policy entitled \u201cPhysicians and the Ontario Human Rights Code.\u201d That policy informed physicians that they should be prepared to \u201cset aside their personal beliefs\u201d in providing healthcare. It warned that the Human Rights Code has no defence for discriminatory refusals of medical services, …<\/p>\n","protected":false},"author":523,"featured_media":3171,"comment_status":"open","ping_status":"open","sticky":false,"template":"","format":"standard","meta":{"_exactmetrics_skip_tracking":false,"_exactmetrics_sitenote_active":false,"_exactmetrics_sitenote_note":"","_exactmetrics_sitenote_category":0,"_monsterinsights_skip_tracking":false,"_monsterinsights_sitenote_active":false,"_monsterinsights_sitenote_note":"","_monsterinsights_sitenote_category":0,"footnotes":""},"categories":[35,34],"tags":[],"_links":{"self":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/3169"}],"collection":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts"}],"about":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/types\/post"}],"author":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/users\/523"}],"replies":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/comments?post=3169"}],"version-history":[{"count":8,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/3169\/revisions"}],"predecessor-version":[{"id":3181,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/3169\/revisions\/3181"}],"wp:featuredmedia":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media\/3171"}],"wp:attachment":[{"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media?parent=3169"}],"wp:term":[{"taxonomy":"category","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/categories?post=3169"},{"taxonomy":"post_tag","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/www.ruleoflaw.ca\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/tags?post=3169"}],"curies":[{"name":"wp","href":"https:\/\/api.w.org\/{rel}","templated":true}]}}